地球为什么自转| 白居易号什么居士| 乳腺囊肿有什么症状| 术后血压低什么原因| bml是什么意思| 大枣枸杞泡水喝有什么好处| hcg是检查什么的| 脚后跟开裂是什么原因| 熬夜伤什么器官| 玮五行属什么| 猫睡在枕头旁说明什么| 社畜什么意思| 飞机为什么能飞上天| 铁罗汉是什么茶| 萎缩性胃炎吃什么药效果好| 朗格手表什么档次| 秦始皇为什么焚书坑儒| 尿路感染有什么症状| daily什么意思| 下压高是什么原因引起的| 复位是什么意思| 火眼金睛是什么生肖| 甲状腺什么症状| 身份证什么时候开始有的| 有氧运动和无氧运动有什么区别| 白羊和什么星座最配| 体检前一天要注意什么| 哈怂是什么意思| 掉头发缺什么维生素| 过敏性鼻炎挂什么科| 韩国为什么叫韩国| 奇葩什么意思| 胸前出汗多是什么原因| 观音成道日是什么意思| 为什么小孩子经常流鼻血| 男人精子少吃什么药| 降压灵又叫什么| 卡哇伊是什么意思| 日龙包是什么意思| 脱发严重应该去医院挂什么科| 数不胜数是什么生肖| 为什么体重一直下降| 佳字属于五行属什么| 烤瓷牙和全瓷牙有什么区别| egm是什么意思| 月经血块多是什么原因| 下线是什么意思| 一个金字旁一个先读什么| 欲言又止的欲什么意思| 幽门螺旋杆菌什么意思| 什么叫道德绑架| 螃蟹和什么不能一起吃| 高频听力损失意味什么| 什么手表品牌最好| 什么叫熬夜| 风俗是什么意思| 堆肥是什么意思| 血粘度查什么项目| 怀孕初期要注意什么| 17年属什么生肖| 杨五行属什么| 什么酷暑| 男人梦见鱼是什么征兆| 头上长痣代表什么| 开水烫伤用什么药膏好得快| 血脂四项包括什么| 自戕是什么意思| 一个六一个允念什么| 9月21号是什么日子| 伤风流鼻涕吃什么药好| 便秘什么原因引起的| 男女更年期分别在什么年龄| 胆囊炎是什么原因引起的| ab型血和o型血的孩子是什么血型| 肛门痒擦什么药| 双离合什么意思| 舌头尖有小红点这是什么症状| 经常腹痛什么原因| 夜间睡觉口干口苦是什么原因| 驴肉不能和什么一起吃| 天荒地老什么意思| a醇对皮肤有什么作用| 小孩子黑眼圈重是什么原因| 118号是什么星座| 什么品牌的床好| 能戒烟的男人什么性格| 杜甫号什么| 寒凝血瘀吃什么中成药| 烂好人什么意思| 颈椎疼挂什么科| 九月29号是什么星座| 饮片是什么意思| 西药是用什么材料做的| 冗长是什么意思| 感冒喉咙痛吃什么药好| 弢是什么意思| 关节炎挂什么科| 知青为什么要下乡| 清明上河图描绘的是什么季节的景象| 0206是什么星座| siri什么意思| 牙结石不除有什么危害| 天什么云什么| 角化型脚气用什么药膏| 肌红蛋白高是什么原因| 欧洲为什么没有统一| 什么血型是万能血型| 不完全骨折是什么意思| 什么是沉香木| 四面八方指什么生肖| 私生子是什么意思| 女人吃什么疏肝理气| 为什么耳朵后面会臭| 喉结是什么| 喉咙痛不能吃什么东西| 抗核抗体阳性说明什么| 龟头炎什么症状| 西洋参不适合什么人吃| ru是什么意思| 飞机联程票是什么意思| 舌头发热是什么原因| 菠萝什么季节成熟| 中午喜鹊叫有什么预兆| xxoo什么意思| 开心的动物是什么生肖| 绿色痰液是什么感染| 胡人是什么民族| 丹参滴丸治什么病| 男孩取什么名字好听又有贵气| 吃过榴莲不能吃什么| 鼻炎看什么科| 胸是什么| 鸡属于什么类动物| 感冒头疼是什么原因| 前世是什么意思| 小孩腹泻吃什么药好得快| 什么力竭| 一月8日是什么星座| 12月14日是什么星座| 闲鱼卖出的东西钱什么时候到账| 为非作歹是什么意思| 毓字五行属什么| 空气湿度是什么意思| 1988是什么年| 吃什么可以去湿气| 女人左下眼皮跳是什么预兆| 脚脖子浮肿是什么原因引起的| 跪安是什么意思| 脂肪肝要注意什么| 方可以加什么偏旁| 手关节疼痛挂什么科| 电轴左偏是什么意思| 细菌感染是什么引起的| 粽子的叶子是什么叶| 什么是小数| 感冒喉咙痛吃什么药好| 男人喝什么茶壮阳| 九二共识是什么意思| 95年的属什么生肖| 虾青素有什么功效| 什么叫匝道| 腰间盘突出睡觉什么姿势好| 癌胚抗原是什么| 肺结节是什么症状| 国企董事长是什么级别| 孙子的儿子叫什么| 金银花什么时候采摘最好| 相生相克是什么意思| 凤凰指什么生肖| 王羲之的儿子叫什么名字| 掉头发吃什么| 蟑螂对人体有什么危害| 宫颈囊肿多发是什么意思| 吃什么药可以延长时间| 1129什么星座| 湿热吃什么水果| 长沙有什么景点| 男士睾丸疼是什么原因| 陆地上最重的动物是什么| 吃头孢不能吃什么| 什么的照射| 广东话扑街是什么意思| 斯德哥尔摩综合征是什么| 吃止疼药有什么副作用| 7月15是什么节日| 玉戴久了会有什么变化| 坐月子什么不能吃| 梦魇是什么原因造成的| 肉鸽是什么意思| 痔疮吃什么消炎药好得快| 中毒了吃什么解毒| 黑裤子配什么颜色上衣| 喉咙痛可以吃什么水果| 嗓子疼咳嗽挂什么科| 射进去是什么感觉| 电风扇不转是什么原因| 流清鼻涕吃什么药| 常青藤是什么意思| 急火攻心是什么生肖| 总爱睡觉是什么原因| 乳房是什么| 伽是什么意思| 卵巢早衰是什么引起的| 破日是什么意思| 七月有什么节日| 小便浑浊是什么原因| 什么是亚麻籽| 凌空什么| 三点水一个分读什么| 生忌是什么意思| 胃气上逆吃什么药| 一个山一个脊念什么| 中秋节什么时候| 血糖在化验单上叫什么| 牙槽骨吸收是什么意思| 什么情况下需要做造影| 罄竹难书的罄什么意思| ab型rh阳性是什么意思| 皮肤偏黄适合穿什么颜色的衣服| 游戏黑洞是什么意思| 观察是什么意思| 三五成群是什么意思| 天干指的是什么| 为什么要穿内裤| 月经提前十几天是什么原因| 家财万贯是什么生肖| 什么叫梗| 一什么猪| 阴道炎应该吃什么药| 浓鼻涕吃什么药| 五花八门是什么生肖| 国字五行属什么| beams是什么品牌| 强痛定又叫什么| 背锅侠是什么意思| 用盐水洗脸有什么好处和坏处| 为什么身上会出现淤青| 乘务长是干什么的| 终止是什么意思| 1984年属鼠是什么命| 淀粉酶高是什么原因| 失去味觉是什么原因| 左侧卵巢多囊样改变什么意思| 诸侯国是什么意思| 是什么部首| 前列腺在哪里男人的什么部位| 脑梗是由什么引起的| 眩晕吃什么药好| 秋葵不适宜什么人吃| 曦字五行属什么| 天线宝宝都叫什么名字| 备孕叶酸什么时候吃最好| 传导阻滞是什么意思| 怕痒的男人意味着什么| 绝症是什么意思| 支气管炎哮喘吃什么药| 姬松茸和什么煲汤最佳| 眷属是什么意思| 经期延长是什么原因引起的| 暨怎么读什么意思| p波高尖代表什么| 中国劲酒有什么功效| 小狗需要打什么疫苗| 坐立不安是什么意思| 百度Jump to content

父母因抚养费起纠纷 8岁女童被弃冬日街头抚养费遗弃

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
百度 挺好的。

In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variables are the truth values true and false, usually denoted by 1 and 0, whereas in elementary algebra the values of the variables are numbers. Second, Boolean algebra uses logical operators such as conjunction (and) denoted as , disjunction (or) denoted as , and negation (not) denoted as ?. Elementary algebra, on the other hand, uses arithmetic operators such as addition, multiplication, subtraction, and division. Boolean algebra is therefore a formal way of describing logical operations in the same way that elementary algebra describes numerical operations.

Boolean algebra was introduced by George Boole in his first book The Mathematical Analysis of Logic (1847),[1] and set forth more fully in his An Investigation of the Laws of Thought (1854).[2] According to Huntington, the term Boolean algebra was first suggested by Henry M. Sheffer in 1913,[3] although Charles Sanders Peirce gave the title "A Boolian [sic] Algebra with One Constant" to the first chapter of his "The Simplest Mathematics" in 1880.[4] Boolean algebra has been fundamental in the development of digital electronics, and is provided for in all modern programming languages. It is also used in set theory and statistics.[5]

History

[edit]

A precursor of Boolean algebra was Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz's algebra of concepts. The usage of binary in relation to the I Ching was central to Leibniz's characteristica universalis. It eventually created the foundations of algebra of concepts.[6] Leibniz's algebra of concepts is deductively equivalent to the Boolean algebra of sets.[7]

Boole's algebra predated the modern developments in abstract algebra and mathematical logic; it is however seen as connected to the origins of both fields.[8] In an abstract setting, Boolean algebra was perfected in the late 19th century by Jevons, Schr?der, Huntington and others, until it reached the modern conception of an (abstract) mathematical structure.[8] For example, the empirical observation that one can manipulate expressions in the algebra of sets, by translating them into expressions in Boole's algebra, is explained in modern terms by saying that the algebra of sets is a Boolean algebra (note the indefinite article). In fact, M. H. Stone proved in 1936 that every Boolean algebra is isomorphic to a field of sets.[9][10]

In the 1930s, while studying switching circuits, Claude Shannon observed that one could also apply the rules of Boole's algebra in this setting,[11] and he introduced switching algebra as a way to analyze and design circuits by algebraic means in terms of logic gates. Shannon already had at his disposal the abstract mathematical apparatus, thus he cast his switching algebra as the two-element Boolean algebra. In modern circuit engineering settings, there is little need to consider other Boolean algebras, thus "switching algebra" and "Boolean algebra" are often used interchangeably.[12][13][14]

Efficient implementation of Boolean functions is a fundamental problem in the design of combinational logic circuits. Modern electronic design automation tools for very-large-scale integration (VLSI) circuits often rely on an efficient representation of Boolean functions known as (reduced ordered) binary decision diagrams (BDD) for logic synthesis and formal verification.[15]

Logic sentences that can be expressed in classical propositional calculus have an equivalent expression in Boolean algebra. Thus, Boolean logic is sometimes used to denote propositional calculus performed in this way.[16][17][18] Boolean algebra is not sufficient to capture logic formulas using quantifiers, like those from first-order logic.

Although the development of mathematical logic did not follow Boole's program, the connection between his algebra and logic was later put on firm ground in the setting of algebraic logic, which also studies the algebraic systems of many other logics.[8] The problem of determining whether the variables of a given Boolean (propositional) formula can be assigned in such a way as to make the formula evaluate to true is called the Boolean satisfiability problem (SAT), and is of importance to theoretical computer science, being the first problem shown to be NP-complete. The closely related model of computation known as a Boolean circuit relates time complexity (of an algorithm) to circuit complexity.

Values

[edit]

Whereas expressions denote mainly numbers in elementary algebra, in Boolean algebra, they denote the truth values false and true. These values are represented with the bits, 0 and 1. They do not behave like the integers 0 and 1, for which 1 + 1 = 2, but may be identified with the elements of the two-element field GF(2), that is, integer arithmetic modulo 2, for which 1 + 1 = 0. Addition and multiplication then play the Boolean roles of XOR (exclusive-or) and AND (conjunction), respectively, with disjunction xy (inclusive-or) definable as x + y ? xy and negation ?x as 1 ? x. In GF(2), ? may be replaced by +, since they denote the same operation; however, this way of writing Boolean operations allows applying the usual arithmetic operations of integers (this may be useful when using a programming language in which GF(2) is not implemented).

Boolean algebra also deals with functions which have their values in the set {0,1}. A sequence of bits is a commonly used example of such a function. Another common example is the totality of subsets of a set E: to a subset F of E, one can define the indicator function that takes the value 1 on F, and 0 outside F. The most general example is the set elements of a Boolean algebra, with all of the foregoing being instances thereof.

As with elementary algebra, the purely equational part of the theory may be developed, without considering explicit values for the variables.[19]

Operations

[edit]

Basic operations

[edit]

While elementary algebra has four operations (addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division), the Boolean algebra has only three basic operations: conjunction, disjunction, and negation, expressed with the corresponding binary operators AND () and OR () and the unary operator NOT (), collectively referred to as Boolean operators.[20] Variables in Boolean algebra that store the logical value of 0 and 1 are called the Boolean variables. They are used to store either true or false values.[21] The basic operations on Boolean variables x and y are defined as follows:

Alternatively, the values of xy, xy, and ?x can be expressed by tabulating their values with truth tables as follows:[22]

When used in expressions, the operators are applied according to the precedence rules. As with elementary algebra, expressions in parentheses are evaluated first, following the precedence rules.[23]

If the truth values 0 and 1 are interpreted as integers, these operations may be expressed with the ordinary operations of arithmetic (where x + y uses addition and xy uses multiplication), or by the minimum/maximum functions:

One might consider that only negation and one of the two other operations are basic because of the following identities that allow one to define conjunction in terms of negation and the disjunction, and vice versa (De Morgan's laws):[24]

Secondary operations

[edit]

Operations composed from the basic operations include, among others, the following:

Material conditional:
Material biconditional:
Exclusive OR (XOR):

These definitions give rise to the following truth tables giving the values of these operations for all four possible inputs.

Secondary operations. Table 1
0 0 1 0 1
1 0 0 1 0
0 1 1 1 0
1 1 1 0 1
Material conditional
The first operation, x → y, or Cxy, is called material implication. If x is true, then the result of expression x → y is taken to be that of y (e.g. if x is true and y is false, then x → y is also false). But if x is false, then the value of y can be ignored; however, the operation must return some Boolean value and there are only two choices. So by definition, x → y is true when x is false (relevance logic rejects this definition, by viewing an implication with a false premise as something other than either true or false).
Exclusive OR (XOR)
The second operation, x ⊕ y, or Jxy, is called exclusive or (often abbreviated as XOR) to distinguish it from disjunction as the inclusive kind. It excludes the possibility of both x and y being true (e.g. see table): if both are true then result is false. Defined in terms of arithmetic it is addition where mod 2 is 1 + 1 = 0.
Logical equivalence
The third operation, the complement of exclusive or, is equivalence or Boolean equality: x ≡ y, or Exy, is true just when x and y have the same value. Hence x ⊕ y as its complement can be understood as x ≠ y, being true just when x and y are different. Thus, its counterpart in arithmetic mod 2 is x + y. Equivalence's counterpart in arithmetic mod 2 is x + y + 1.

Laws

[edit]

A law of Boolean algebra is an identity such as x ∨ (yz) = (xy) ∨ z between two Boolean terms, where a Boolean term is defined as an expression built up from variables and the constants 0 and 1 using the operations ∧, ∨, and ?. The concept can be extended to terms involving other Boolean operations such as ⊕, →, and ≡, but such extensions are unnecessary for the purposes to which the laws are put. Such purposes include the definition of a Boolean algebra as any model of the Boolean laws, and as a means for deriving new laws from old as in the derivation of x ∨ (yz) = x ∨ (zy) from yz = zy (as treated in § Axiomatizing Boolean algebra).

Monotone laws

[edit]

Boolean algebra satisfies many of the same laws as ordinary algebra when one matches up ∨ with addition and ∧ with multiplication. In particular the following laws are common to both kinds of algebra:[25][26]

Associativity of :
Associativity of :
Commutativity of :
Commutativity of :
Distributivity of over :
Identity for :
Identity for :
Annihilator for :

The following laws hold in Boolean algebra, but not in ordinary algebra:

Annihilator for :
Idempotence of :
Idempotence of :
Absorption 1:
Absorption 2:
Distributivity of over :

Taking x = 2 in the third law above shows that it is not an ordinary algebra law, since 2 × 2 = 4. The remaining five laws can be falsified in ordinary algebra by taking all variables to be 1. For example, in absorption law 1, the left hand side would be 1(1 + 1) = 2, while the right hand side would be 1 (and so on).

All of the laws treated thus far have been for conjunction and disjunction. These operations have the property that changing either argument either leaves the output unchanged, or the output changes in the same way as the input. Equivalently, changing any variable from 0 to 1 never results in the output changing from 1 to 0. Operations with this property are said to be monotone. Thus the axioms thus far have all been for monotonic Boolean logic. Nonmonotonicity enters via complement ? as follows.[5]

Nonmonotone laws

[edit]

The complement operation is defined by the following two laws.

All properties of negation including the laws below follow from the above two laws alone.[5]

In both ordinary and Boolean algebra, negation works by exchanging pairs of elements, hence in both algebras it satisfies the double negation law (also called involution law)

But whereas ordinary algebra satisfies the two laws

Boolean algebra satisfies De Morgan's laws:

Completeness

[edit]

The laws listed above define Boolean algebra, in the sense that they entail the rest of the subject. The laws complementation 1 and 2, together with the monotone laws, suffice for this purpose and can therefore be taken as one possible complete set of laws or axiomatization of Boolean algebra. Every law of Boolean algebra follows logically from these axioms. Furthermore, Boolean algebras can then be defined as the models of these axioms as treated in § Boolean algebras.

Writing down further laws of Boolean algebra cannot give rise to any new consequences of these axioms, nor can it rule out any model of them. In contrast, in a list of some but not all of the same laws, there could have been Boolean laws that did not follow from those on the list, and moreover there would have been models of the listed laws that were not Boolean algebras.

This axiomatization is by no means the only one, or even necessarily the most natural given that attention was not paid as to whether some of the axioms followed from others, but there was simply a choice to stop when enough laws had been noticed, treated further in § Axiomatizing Boolean algebra. Or the intermediate notion of axiom can be sidestepped altogether by defining a Boolean law directly as any tautology, understood as an equation that holds for all values of its variables over 0 and 1.[27][28] All these definitions of Boolean algebra can be shown to be equivalent.

Duality principle

[edit]

Principle: If {X, R} is a partially ordered set, then {X, R(inverse)} is also a partially ordered set.

There is nothing special about the choice of symbols for the values of Boolean algebra. 0 and 1 could be renamed to α and β, and as long as it was done consistently throughout, it would still be Boolean algebra, albeit with some obvious cosmetic differences.

But suppose 0 and 1 were renamed 1 and 0 respectively. Then it would still be Boolean algebra, and moreover operating on the same values. However, it would not be identical to our original Boolean algebra because now ∨ behaves the way ∧ used to do and vice versa. So there are still some cosmetic differences to show that the notation has been changed, despite the fact that 0s and 1s are still being used.

But if in addition to interchanging the names of the values, the names of the two binary operations are also interchanged, now there is no trace of what was done. The end product is completely indistinguishable from what was started with. The columns for xy and xy in the truth tables have changed places, but that switch is immaterial.

When values and operations can be paired up in a way that leaves everything important unchanged when all pairs are switched simultaneously, the members of each pair are called dual to each other. Thus 0 and 1 are dual, and ∧ and ∨ are dual. The duality principle, also called De Morgan duality, asserts that Boolean algebra is unchanged when all dual pairs are interchanged.

One change not needed to make as part of this interchange was to complement. Complement is a self-dual operation. The identity or do-nothing operation x (copy the input to the output) is also self-dual. A more complicated example of a self-dual operation is (xy) ∨ (yz) ∨ (zx). There is no self-dual binary operation that depends on both its arguments. A composition of self-dual operations is a self-dual operation. For example, if f(x, y, z) = (xy) ∨ (yz) ∨ (zx), then f(f(x, y, z), x, t) is a self-dual operation of four arguments x, y, z, t.

The principle of duality can be explained from a group theory perspective by the fact that there are exactly four functions that are one-to-one mappings (automorphisms) of the set of Boolean polynomials back to itself: the identity function, the complement function, the dual function and the contradual function (complemented dual). These four functions form a group under function composition, isomorphic to the Klein four-group, acting on the set of Boolean polynomials. Walter Gottschalk remarked that consequently a more appropriate name for the phenomenon would be the principle (or square) of quaternality.[5]:?21–22?

Diagrammatic representations

[edit]

Venn diagrams

[edit]

A Venn diagram[29] can be used as a representation of a Boolean operation using shaded overlapping regions. There is one region for each variable, all circular in the examples here. The interior and exterior of region x corresponds respectively to the values 1 (true) and 0 (false) for variable x. The shading indicates the value of the operation for each combination of regions, with dark denoting 1 and light 0 (some authors use the opposite convention).

The three Venn diagrams in the figure below represent respectively conjunction xy, disjunction xy, and complement ?x.

Figure 2. Venn diagrams for conjunction, disjunction, and complement

For conjunction, the region inside both circles is shaded to indicate that xy is 1 when both variables are 1. The other regions are left unshaded to indicate that xy is 0 for the other three combinations.

The second diagram represents disjunction xy by shading those regions that lie inside either or both circles. The third diagram represents complement ?x by shading the region not inside the circle.

While we have not shown the Venn diagrams for the constants 0 and 1, they are trivial, being respectively a white box and a dark box, neither one containing a circle. However, we could put a circle for x in those boxes, in which case each would denote a function of one argument, x, which returns the same value independently of x, called a constant function. As far as their outputs are concerned, constants and constant functions are indistinguishable; the difference is that a constant takes no arguments, called a zeroary or nullary operation, while a constant function takes one argument, which it ignores, and is a unary operation.

Venn diagrams are helpful in visualizing laws. The commutativity laws for ∧ and ∨ can be seen from the symmetry of the diagrams: a binary operation that was not commutative would not have a symmetric diagram because interchanging x and y would have the effect of reflecting the diagram horizontally and any failure of commutativity would then appear as a failure of symmetry.

Idempotence of ∧ and ∨ can be visualized by sliding the two circles together and noting that the shaded area then becomes the whole circle, for both ∧ and ∨.

To see the first absorption law, x ∧ (xy) = x, start with the diagram in the middle for xy and note that the portion of the shaded area in common with the x circle is the whole of the x circle. For the second absorption law, x ∨ (xy) = x, start with the left diagram for xy and note that shading the whole of the x circle results in just the x circle being shaded, since the previous shading was inside the x circle.

The double negation law can be seen by complementing the shading in the third diagram for ?x, which shades the x circle.

To visualize the first De Morgan's law, (?x) ∧ (?y) = ?(xy), start with the middle diagram for xy and complement its shading so that only the region outside both circles is shaded, which is what the right hand side of the law describes. The result is the same as if we shaded that region which is both outside the x circle and outside the y circle, i.e. the conjunction of their exteriors, which is what the left hand side of the law describes.

The second De Morgan's law, (?x) ∨ (?y) = ?(xy), works the same way with the two diagrams interchanged.

The first complement law, x ∧ ?x = 0, says that the interior and exterior of the x circle have no overlap. The second complement law, x ∨ ?x = 1, says that everything is either inside or outside the x circle.

Digital logic gates

[edit]

Digital logic is the application of the Boolean algebra of 0 and 1 to electronic hardware consisting of logic gates connected to form a circuit diagram. Each gate implements a Boolean operation, and is depicted schematically by a shape indicating the operation. The shapes associated with the gates for conjunction (AND-gates), disjunction (OR-gates), and complement (inverters) are as follows:[30]

From left to right: AND, OR, and NOT gates.

The lines on the left of each gate represent input wires or ports. The value of the input is represented by a voltage on the lead. For so-called "active-high" logic, 0 is represented by a voltage close to zero or "ground," while 1 is represented by a voltage close to the supply voltage; active-low reverses this. The line on the right of each gate represents the output port, which normally follows the same voltage conventions as the input ports.

Complement is implemented with an inverter gate. The triangle denotes the operation that simply copies the input to the output; the small circle on the output denotes the actual inversion complementing the input. The convention of putting such a circle on any port means that the signal passing through this port is complemented on the way through, whether it is an input or output port.

The duality principle, or De Morgan's laws, can be understood as asserting that complementing all three ports of an AND gate converts it to an OR gate and vice versa, as shown in Figure 4 below. Complementing both ports of an inverter however leaves the operation unchanged.

More generally, one may complement any of the eight subsets of the three ports of either an AND or OR gate. The resulting sixteen possibilities give rise to only eight Boolean operations, namely those with an odd number of 1s in their truth table. There are eight such because the "odd-bit-out" can be either 0 or 1 and can go in any of four positions in the truth table. There being sixteen binary Boolean operations, this must leave eight operations with an even number of 1s in their truth tables. Two of these are the constants 0 and 1 (as binary operations that ignore both their inputs); four are the operations that depend nontrivially on exactly one of their two inputs, namely x, y, ?x, and ?y; and the remaining two are xy (XOR) and its complement xy.

Boolean algebras

[edit]

The term "algebra" denotes both a subject, namely the subject of algebra, and an object, namely an algebraic structure. Whereas the foregoing has addressed the subject of Boolean algebra, this section deals with mathematical objects called Boolean algebras, defined in full generality as any model of the Boolean laws. We begin with a special case of the notion definable without reference to the laws, namely concrete Boolean algebras, and then give the formal definition of the general notion.

Concrete Boolean algebras

[edit]

A concrete Boolean algebra or field of sets is any nonempty set of subsets of a given set X closed under the set operations of union, intersection, and complement relative to X.[5]

(Historically X itself was required to be nonempty as well to exclude the degenerate or one-element Boolean algebra, which is the one exception to the rule that all Boolean algebras satisfy the same equations since the degenerate algebra satisfies every equation. However, this exclusion conflicts with the preferred purely equational definition of "Boolean algebra", there being no way to rule out the one-element algebra using only equations— 0 ≠ 1 does not count, being a negated equation. Hence modern authors allow the degenerate Boolean algebra and let X be empty.)

Example 1. The power set 2X of X, consisting of all subsets of X. Here X may be any set: empty, finite, infinite, or even uncountable.

Example 2. The empty set and X. This two-element algebra shows that a concrete Boolean algebra can be finite even when it consists of subsets of an infinite set. It can be seen that every field of subsets of X must contain the empty set and X. Hence no smaller example is possible, other than the degenerate algebra obtained by taking X to be empty so as to make the empty set and X coincide.

Example 3. The set of finite and cofinite sets of integers, where a cofinite set is one omitting only finitely many integers. This is clearly closed under complement, and is closed under union because the union of a cofinite set with any set is cofinite, while the union of two finite sets is finite. Intersection behaves like union with "finite" and "cofinite" interchanged. This example is countably infinite because there are only countably many finite sets of integers.

Example 4. For a less trivial example of the point made by example 2, consider a Venn diagram formed by n closed curves partitioning the diagram into 2n regions, and let X be the (infinite) set of all points in the plane not on any curve but somewhere within the diagram. The interior of each region is thus an infinite subset of X, and every point in X is in exactly one region. Then the set of all 22n possible unions of regions (including the empty set obtained as the union of the empty set of regions and X obtained as the union of all 2n regions) is closed under union, intersection, and complement relative to X and therefore forms a concrete Boolean algebra. Again, there are finitely many subsets of an infinite set forming a concrete Boolean algebra, with example 2 arising as the case n = 0 of no curves.

Subsets as bit vectors

[edit]

A subset Y of X can be identified with an indexed family of bits with index set X, with the bit indexed by xX being 1 or 0 according to whether or not xY. (This is the so-called characteristic function notion of a subset.) For example, a 32-bit computer word consists of 32 bits indexed by the set {0,1,2,...,31}, with 0 and 31 indexing the low and high order bits respectively. For a smaller example, if ?? where a, b, c are viewed as bit positions in that order from left to right, the eight subsets {}, {c}, {b}, {b,c}, {a}, {a,c}, {a,b}, and {a,b,c} of X can be identified with the respective bit vectors 000, 001, 010, 011, 100, 101, 110, and 111. Bit vectors indexed by the set of natural numbers are infinite sequences of bits, while those indexed by the reals in the unit interval [0,1] are packed too densely to be able to write conventionally but nonetheless form well-defined indexed families (imagine coloring every point of the interval [0,1] either black or white independently; the black points then form an arbitrary subset of [0,1]).

From this bit vector viewpoint, a concrete Boolean algebra can be defined equivalently as a nonempty set of bit vectors all of the same length (more generally, indexed by the same set) and closed under the bit vector operations of bitwise ∧, ∨, and ?, as in 1010∧0110 = 0010, 1010∨0110 = 1110, and ?1010 = 0101, the bit vector realizations of intersection, union, and complement respectively.

Prototypical Boolean algebra

[edit]

The set {0,1} and its Boolean operations as treated above can be understood as the special case of bit vectors of length one, which by the identification of bit vectors with subsets can also be understood as the two subsets of a one-element set. This is called the prototypical Boolean algebra, justified by the following observation.

The laws satisfied by all nondegenerate concrete Boolean algebras coincide with those satisfied by the prototypical Boolean algebra.

This observation is proved as follows. Certainly any law satisfied by all concrete Boolean algebras is satisfied by the prototypical one since it is concrete. Conversely any law that fails for some concrete Boolean algebra must have failed at a particular bit position, in which case that position by itself furnishes a one-bit counterexample to that law. Nondegeneracy ensures the existence of at least one bit position because there is only one empty bit vector.

The final goal of the next section can be understood as eliminating "concrete" from the above observation. That goal is reached via the stronger observation that, up to isomorphism, all Boolean algebras are concrete.

Boolean algebras: the definition

[edit]

The Boolean algebras so far have all been concrete, consisting of bit vectors or equivalently of subsets of some set. Such a Boolean algebra consists of a set and operations on that set which can be shown to satisfy the laws of Boolean algebra.

Instead of showing that the Boolean laws are satisfied, we can instead postulate a set X, two binary operations on X, and one unary operation, and require that those operations satisfy the laws of Boolean algebra. The elements of X need not be bit vectors or subsets but can be anything at all. This leads to the more general abstract definition.

A Boolean algebra is any set with binary operations ∧ and ∨ and a unary operation ? thereon satisfying the Boolean laws.[31]

For the purposes of this definition it is irrelevant how the operations came to satisfy the laws, whether by fiat or proof. All concrete Boolean algebras satisfy the laws (by proof rather than fiat), whence every concrete Boolean algebra is a Boolean algebra according to our definitions. This axiomatic definition of a Boolean algebra as a set and certain operations satisfying certain laws or axioms by fiat is entirely analogous to the abstract definitions of group, ring, field etc. characteristic of modern or abstract algebra.

Given any complete axiomatization of Boolean algebra, such as the axioms for a complemented distributive lattice, a sufficient condition for an algebraic structure of this kind to satisfy all the Boolean laws is that it satisfy just those axioms. The following is therefore an equivalent definition.

A Boolean algebra is a complemented distributive lattice.

The section on axiomatization lists other axiomatizations, any of which can be made the basis of an equivalent definition.

Representable Boolean algebras

[edit]

Although every concrete Boolean algebra is a Boolean algebra, not every Boolean algebra need be concrete. Let n be a square-free positive integer, one not divisible by the square of an integer, for example 30 but not 12. The operations of greatest common divisor, least common multiple, and division into n (that is, ?x = n/x), can be shown to satisfy all the Boolean laws when their arguments range over the positive divisors of n. Hence those divisors form a Boolean algebra. These divisors are not subsets of a set, making the divisors of n a Boolean algebra that is not concrete according to our definitions.

However, if each divisor of n is represented by the set of its prime factors, this nonconcrete Boolean algebra is isomorphic to the concrete Boolean algebra consisting of all sets of prime factors of n, with union corresponding to least common multiple, intersection to greatest common divisor, and complement to division into n. So this example, while not technically concrete, is at least "morally" concrete via this representation, called an isomorphism. This example is an instance of the following notion.

A Boolean algebra is called representable when it is isomorphic to a concrete Boolean algebra.

The next question is answered positively as follows.

Every Boolean algebra is representable.

That is, up to isomorphism, abstract and concrete Boolean algebras are the same thing. This result depends on the Boolean prime ideal theorem, a choice principle slightly weaker than the axiom of choice. This strong relationship implies a weaker result strengthening the observation in the previous subsection to the following easy consequence of representability.

The laws satisfied by all Boolean algebras coincide with those satisfied by the prototypical Boolean algebra.

It is weaker in the sense that it does not of itself imply representability. Boolean algebras are special here, for example a relation algebra is a Boolean algebra with additional structure but it is not the case that every relation algebra is representable in the sense appropriate to relation algebras.

Axiomatizing Boolean algebra

[edit]

The above definition of an abstract Boolean algebra as a set together with operations satisfying "the" Boolean laws raises the question of what those laws are. A simplistic answer is "all Boolean laws", which can be defined as all equations that hold for the Boolean algebra of 0 and 1. However, since there are infinitely many such laws, this is not a satisfactory answer in practice, leading to the question of it suffices to require only finitely many laws to hold.

In the case of Boolean algebras, the answer is "yes": the finitely many equations listed above are sufficient. Thus, Boolean algebra is said to be finitely axiomatizable or finitely based.

Moreover, the number of equations needed can be further reduced. To begin with, some of the above laws are implied by some of the others. A sufficient subset of the above laws consists of the pairs of associativity, commutativity, and absorption laws, distributivity of ∧ over ∨ (or the other distributivity law—one suffices), and the two complement laws. In fact, this is the traditional axiomatization of Boolean algebra as a complemented distributive lattice.

By introducing additional laws not listed above, it becomes possible to shorten the list of needed equations yet further; for instance, with the vertical bar representing the Sheffer stroke operation, the single axiom is sufficient to completely axiomatize Boolean algebra. It is also possible to find longer single axioms using more conventional operations; see Minimal axioms for Boolean algebra.[32]

Propositional logic

[edit]

Propositional logic is a logical system that is intimately connected to Boolean algebra.[5] Many syntactic concepts of Boolean algebra carry over to propositional logic with only minor changes in notation and terminology, while the semantics of propositional logic are defined via Boolean algebras in a way that the tautologies (theorems) of propositional logic correspond to equational theorems of Boolean algebra.

Syntactically, every Boolean term corresponds to a propositional formula of propositional logic. In this translation between Boolean algebra and propositional logic, Boolean variables x, y, ... become propositional variables (or atoms) P, Q, ... Boolean terms such as xy become propositional formulas PQ; 0 becomes false or , and 1 becomes true or ?. It is convenient when referring to generic propositions to use Greek letters Φ, Ψ, ... as metavariables (variables outside the language of propositional calculus, used when talking about propositional calculus) to denote propositions.

The semantics of propositional logic rely on truth assignments. The essential idea of a truth assignment is that the propositional variables are mapped to elements of a fixed Boolean algebra, and then the truth value of a propositional formula using these letters is the element of the Boolean algebra that is obtained by computing the value of the Boolean term corresponding to the formula. In classical semantics, only the two-element Boolean algebra is used, while in Boolean-valued semantics arbitrary Boolean algebras are considered. A tautology is a propositional formula that is assigned truth value 1 by every truth assignment of its propositional variables to an arbitrary Boolean algebra (or, equivalently, every truth assignment to the two element Boolean algebra).

These semantics permit a translation between tautologies of propositional logic and equational theorems of Boolean algebra. Every tautology Φ of propositional logic can be expressed as the Boolean equation Φ = 1, which will be a theorem of Boolean algebra. Conversely, every theorem Φ = Ψ of Boolean algebra corresponds to the tautologies (Φ ∨ ?Ψ) ∧ (?Φ ∨ Ψ) and (Φ ∧ Ψ) ∨ (?Φ ∧ ?Ψ). If → is in the language, these last tautologies can also be written as (Φ → Ψ) ∧ (Ψ → Φ), or as two separate theorems Φ → Ψ and Ψ → Φ; if ≡ is available, then the single tautology Φ ≡ Ψ can be used.

Applications

[edit]

One motivating application of propositional calculus is the analysis of propositions and deductive arguments in natural language.[33] Whereas the proposition "if x = 3, then x + 1 = 4" depends on the meanings of such symbols as + and 1, the proposition "if x = 3, then x = 3" does not; it is true merely by virtue of its structure, and remains true whether "x = 3" is replaced by "x = 4" or "the moon is made of green cheese." The generic or abstract form of this tautology is "if P, then P," or in the language of Boolean algebra, PP.[citation needed]

Replacing P by x = 3 or any other proposition is called instantiation of P by that proposition. The result of instantiating P in an abstract proposition is called an instance of the proposition. Thus, x = 3 → x = 3 is a tautology by virtue of being an instance of the abstract tautology PP. All occurrences of the instantiated variable must be instantiated with the same proposition, to avoid such nonsense as Px = 3 or x = 3 → x = 4.

Propositional calculus restricts attention to abstract propositions, those built up from propositional variables using Boolean operations. Instantiation is still possible within propositional calculus, but only by instantiating propositional variables by abstract propositions, such as instantiating Q by QP in P → (QP) to yield the instance P → ((QP) → P).

(The availability of instantiation as part of the machinery of propositional calculus avoids the need for metavariables within the language of propositional calculus, since ordinary propositional variables can be considered within the language to denote arbitrary propositions. The metavariables themselves are outside the reach of instantiation, not being part of the language of propositional calculus but rather part of the same language for talking about it that this sentence is written in, where there is a need to be able to distinguish propositional variables and their instantiations as being distinct syntactic entities.)

Deductive systems for propositional logic

[edit]

An axiomatization of propositional calculus is a set of tautologies called axioms and one or more inference rules for producing new tautologies from old. A proof in an axiom system A is a finite nonempty sequence of propositions each of which is either an instance of an axiom of A or follows by some rule of A from propositions appearing earlier in the proof (thereby disallowing circular reasoning). The last proposition is the theorem proved by the proof. Every nonempty initial segment of a proof is itself a proof, whence every proposition in a proof is itself a theorem. An axiomatization is sound when every theorem is a tautology, and complete when every tautology is a theorem.[34]

Sequent calculus

[edit]

Propositional calculus is commonly organized as a Hilbert system, whose operations are just those of Boolean algebra and whose theorems are Boolean tautologies, those Boolean terms equal to the Boolean constant 1. Another form is sequent calculus, which has two sorts, propositions as in ordinary propositional calculus, and pairs of lists of propositions called sequents, such as AB, AC, ... ? A, BC, .... The two halves of a sequent are called the antecedent and the succedent respectively. The customary metavariable denoting an antecedent or part thereof is Γ, and for a succedent Δ; thus Γ, A ? Δ would denote a sequent whose succedent is a list Δ and whose antecedent is a list Γ with an additional proposition A appended after it. The antecedent is interpreted as the conjunction of its propositions, the succedent as the disjunction of its propositions, and the sequent itself as the entailment of the succedent by the antecedent.

Entailment differs from implication in that whereas the latter is a binary operation that returns a value in a Boolean algebra, the former is a binary relation which either holds or does not hold. In this sense, entailment is an external form of implication, meaning external to the Boolean algebra, thinking of the reader of the sequent as also being external and interpreting and comparing antecedents and succedents in some Boolean algebra. The natural interpretation of ? is as ≤ in the partial order of the Boolean algebra defined by xy just when xy = y. This ability to mix external implication ? and internal implication → in the one logic is among the essential differences between sequent calculus and propositional calculus.[35]

Applications

[edit]

Boolean algebra as the calculus of two values is fundamental to computer circuits, computer programming, and mathematical logic, and is also used in other areas of mathematics such as set theory and statistics.[5]

Computers

[edit]

In the early 20th century, several electrical engineers[who?] intuitively recognized that Boolean algebra was analogous to the behavior of certain types of electrical circuits. Claude Shannon formally proved such behavior was logically equivalent to Boolean algebra in his 1937 master's thesis, A Symbolic Analysis of Relay and Switching Circuits.

Today, all modern general-purpose computers perform their functions using two-value Boolean logic; that is, their electrical circuits are a physical manifestation of two-value Boolean logic. They achieve this in various ways: as voltages on wires in high-speed circuits and capacitive storage devices, as orientations of a magnetic domain in ferromagnetic storage devices, as holes in punched cards or paper tape, and so on. (Some early computers used decimal circuits or mechanisms instead of two-valued logic circuits.)

Of course, it is possible to code more than two symbols in any given medium. For example, one might use respectively 0, 1, 2, and 3 volts to code a four-symbol alphabet on a wire, or holes of different sizes in a punched card. In practice, the tight constraints of high speed, small size, and low power combine to make noise a major factor. This makes it hard to distinguish between symbols when there are several possible symbols that could occur at a single site. Rather than attempting to distinguish between four voltages on one wire, digital designers have settled on two voltages per wire, high and low.

Computers use two-value Boolean circuits for the above reasons. The most common computer architectures use ordered sequences of Boolean values, called bits, of 32 or 64 values, e.g. 01101000110101100101010101001011. When programming in machine code, assembly language, and certain other programming languages, programmers work with the low-level digital structure of the data registers. These registers operate on voltages, where zero volts represents Boolean 0, and a reference voltage (often +5 V, +3.3 V, or +1.8 V) represents Boolean 1. Such languages support both numeric operations and logical operations. In this context, "numeric" means that the computer treats sequences of bits as binary numbers (base two numbers) and executes arithmetic operations like add, subtract, multiply, or divide. "Logical" refers to the Boolean logical operations of disjunction, conjunction, and negation between two sequences of bits, in which each bit in one sequence is simply compared to its counterpart in the other sequence. Programmers therefore have the option of working in and applying the rules of either numeric algebra or Boolean algebra as needed. A core differentiating feature between these families of operations is the existence of the carry operation in the first but not the second.

Two-valued logic

[edit]

Other areas where two values is a good choice are the law and mathematics. In everyday relaxed conversation, nuanced or complex answers such as "maybe" or "only on the weekend" are acceptable. In more focused situations such as a court of law or theorem-based mathematics, however, it is deemed advantageous to frame questions so as to admit a simple yes-or-no answer—is the defendant guilty or not guilty, is the proposition true or false—and to disallow any other answer. However, limiting this might prove in practice for the respondent, the principle of the simple yes–no question has become a central feature of both judicial and mathematical logic, making two-valued logic deserving of organization and study in its own right.

A central concept of set theory is membership. An organization may permit multiple degrees of membership, such as novice, associate, and full. With sets, however, an element is either in or out. The candidates for membership in a set work just like the wires in a digital computer: each candidate is either a member or a nonmember, just as each wire is either high or low.

Algebra being a fundamental tool in any area amenable to mathematical treatment, these considerations combine to make the algebra of two values of fundamental importance to computer hardware, mathematical logic, and set theory.

Two-valued logic can be extended to multi-valued logic, notably by replacing the Boolean domain {0, 1} with the unit interval [0,1], in which case rather than only taking values 0 or 1, any value between and including 0 and 1 can be assumed. Algebraically, negation (NOT) is replaced with 1 ? x, conjunction (AND) is replaced with multiplication (xy), and disjunction (OR) is defined via De Morgan's law. Interpreting these values as logical truth values yields a multi-valued logic, which forms the basis for fuzzy logic and probabilistic logic. In these interpretations, a value is interpreted as the "degree" of truth – to what extent a proposition is true, or the probability that the proposition is true.

Boolean operations

[edit]

The original application for Boolean operations was mathematical logic, where it combines the truth values, true or false, of individual formulas.

Natural language

[edit]

Natural languages such as English have words for several Boolean operations, in particular conjunction (and), disjunction (or), negation (not), and implication (implies). But not is synonymous with and not. When used to combine situational assertions such as "the block is on the table" and "cats drink milk", which na?vely are either true or false, the meanings of these logical connectives often have the meaning of their logical counterparts. However, with descriptions of behavior such as "Jim walked through the door", one starts to notice differences such as failure of commutativity, for example, the conjunction of "Jim opened the door" with "Jim walked through the door" in that order is not equivalent to their conjunction in the other order, since and usually means and then in such cases. Questions can be similar: the order "Is the sky blue, and why is the sky blue?" makes more sense than the reverse order. Conjunctive commands about behavior are like behavioral assertions, as in get dressed and go to school. Disjunctive commands such love me or leave me or fish or cut bait tend to be asymmetric via the implication that one alternative is less preferable. Conjoined nouns such as tea and milk generally describe aggregation as with set union while tea or milk is a choice. However, context can reverse these senses, as in your choices are coffee and tea which usually means the same as your choices are coffee or tea (alternatives). Double negation, as in "I don't not like milk", rarely means literally "I do like milk" but rather conveys some sort of hedging, as though to imply that there is a third possibility. "Not not P" can be loosely interpreted as "surely P", and although P necessarily implies "not not P," the converse is suspect in English, much as with intuitionistic logic. In view of the highly idiosyncratic usage of conjunctions in natural languages, Boolean algebra cannot be considered a reliable framework for interpreting them.

Digital logic

[edit]

Boolean operations are used in digital logic to combine the bits carried on individual wires, thereby interpreting them over {0,1}. When a vector of n identical binary gates are used to combine two bit vectors each of n bits, the individual bit operations can be understood collectively as a single operation on values from a Boolean algebra with 2n elements.

Naive set theory

[edit]

Naive set theory interprets Boolean operations as acting on subsets of a given set X. As we saw earlier this behavior exactly parallels the coordinate-wise combinations of bit vectors, with the union of two sets corresponding to the disjunction of two bit vectors and so on.

Video cards

[edit]

The 256-element free Boolean algebra on three generators is deployed in computer displays based on raster graphics, which use bit blit to manipulate whole regions consisting of pixels, relying on Boolean operations to specify how the source region should be combined with the destination, typically with the help of a third region called the mask. Modern video cards offer all 223 = 256 ternary operations for this purpose, with the choice of operation being a one-byte (8-bit) parameter. The constants SRC = 0xaa or 0b10101010, DST = 0xcc or 0b11001100, and MSK = 0xf0 or 0b11110000 allow Boolean operations such as (SRC^DST)&MSK (meaning XOR the source and destination and then AND the result with the mask) to be written directly as a constant denoting a byte calculated at compile time, 0x80 in the (SRC^DST)&MSK example, 0x88 if just SRC^DST, etc. At run time the video card interprets the byte as the raster operation indicated by the original expression in a uniform way that requires remarkably little hardware and which takes time completely independent of the complexity of the expression.

Modeling and CAD

[edit]

Solid modeling systems for computer aided design offer a variety of methods for building objects from other objects, combination by Boolean operations being one of them. In this method the space in which objects exist is understood as a set S of voxels (the three-dimensional analogue of pixels in two-dimensional graphics) and shapes are defined as subsets of S, allowing objects to be combined as sets via union, intersection, etc. One obvious use is in building a complex shape from simple shapes simply as the union of the latter. Another use is in sculpting understood as removal of material: any grinding, milling, routing, or drilling operation that can be performed with physical machinery on physical materials can be simulated on the computer with the Boolean operation x ∧ ?y or x ? y, which in set theory is set difference, remove the elements of y from those of x. Thus given two shapes one to be machined and the other the material to be removed, the result of machining the former to remove the latter is described simply as their set difference.

Boolean searches

[edit]

Search engine queries also employ Boolean logic. For this application, each web page on the Internet may be considered to be an "element" of a "set." The following examples use a syntax supported by Google.[NB 1]

  • Doublequotes are used to combine whitespace-separated words into a single search term.[NB 2]
  • Whitespace is used to specify logical AND, as it is the default operator for joining search terms:
"Search term 1" "Search term 2"
  • The OR keyword is used for logical OR:
"Search term 1" OR "Search term 2"
  • A prefixed minus sign is used for logical NOT:
"Search term 1" ?"Search term 2"

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ Not all search engines support the same query syntax. Additionally, some organizations (such as Google) provide "specialized" search engines that support alternate or extended syntax. (See, Syntax cheatsheet.) The now-defunct Google code search used to support regular expressions but no longer exists.
  2. ^ Doublequote-delimited search terms are called "exact phrase" searches in the Google documentation.

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Boole, George (2025-08-06). The Mathematical Analysis of Logic - Being an Essay Towards a Calculus of Deductive Reasoning.
  2. ^ Boole, George (2003) [1854]. An Investigation of the Laws of Thought. Prometheus Books. ISBN 978-1-59102-089-9.
  3. ^ "The name Boolean algebra (or Boolean 'algebras') for the calculus originated by Boole, extended by Schr?der, and perfected by Whitehead seems to have been first suggested by Sheffer, in 1913." Edward Vermilye Huntington, "New sets of independent postulates for the algebra of logic, with special reference to Whitehead and Russell's Principia mathematica", in Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 35 (1933), 274-304; footnote, page 278.
  4. ^ Peirce, Charles S. (1931). Collected Papers. Vol. 3. Harvard University Press. p. 13. ISBN 978-0-674-13801-8. {{cite book}}: ISBN / Date incompatibility (help)
  5. ^ a b c d e f g Givant, Steven R.; Halmos, Paul Richard (2009). Introduction to Boolean Algebras. Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics, Springer. pp. 21–22. ISBN 978-0-387-40293-2.
  6. ^ Nelson, Eric S. (2011). "The Yijing and Philosophy: From Leibniz to Derrida". Journal of Chinese Philosophy. 38 (3): 377–396. doi:10.1111/j.1540-6253.2011.01661.x.
  7. ^ Lenzen, Wolfgang. "Leibniz: Logic". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  8. ^ a b c Dunn, J. Michael; Hardegree, Gary M. (2001). Algebraic methods in philosophical logic. Oxford University Press. p. 2. ISBN 978-0-19-853192-0.
  9. ^ Bimbó, Katalin; Dunn, J. Michael (2008). Generalized Galois Logics: Relational Semantics of Nonclassical Logical Calculi. CSLI Publications. ISBN 978-1-57586-573-7.
  10. ^ Stone, M. H. (1936). "The Theory of Representation for Boolean Algebras". Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 40 (1): 37–111. doi:10.2307/1989664. ISSN 0002-9947.
  11. ^ Weisstein, Eric W. "Boolean Algebra". mathworld.wolfram.com. Retrieved 2025-08-06.
  12. ^ Balabanian, Norman; Carlson, Bradley (2001). Digital logic design principles. John Wiley. pp. 39–40. ISBN 978-0-471-29351-4., online sample
  13. ^ Rajaraman; Radhakrishnan (2025-08-06). Introduction To Digital Computer Design. PHI Learning Pvt. Ltd. p. 65. ISBN 978-81-203-3409-0.
  14. ^ Camara, John A. (2010). Electrical and Electronics Reference Manual for the Electrical and Computer PE Exam. www.ppi2pass.com. p. 41. ISBN 978-1-59126-166-7.
  15. ^ Shin-ichi Minato, Saburo Muroga (2007). "Chapter 29: Binary Decision Diagrams". In Chen, Wai-Kai (ed.). The VLSI handbook (2 ed.). CRC Press. ISBN 978-0-8493-4199-1.
  16. ^ Parkes, Alan (2002). Introduction to languages, machines and logic: computable languages, abstract machines and formal logic. Springer. p. 276. ISBN 978-1-85233-464-2.
  17. ^ Barwise, Jon; Etchemendy, John; Allwein, Gerard; Barker-Plummer, Dave; Liu, Albert (1999). Language, proof, and logic. CSLI Publications. ISBN 978-1-889119-08-3.
  18. ^ Goertzel, Ben (1994). Chaotic logic: language, thought, and reality from the perspective of complex systems science. Springer. p. 48. ISBN 978-0-306-44690-0.
  19. ^ Halmos, Paul Richard (1963). Lectures on Boolean Algebras. van Nostrand.
  20. ^ Bacon, Jason W. (2011). "Computer Science 315 Lecture Notes". Archived from the original on 2025-08-06. Retrieved 2025-08-06.
  21. ^ "Boolean Algebra - Expression, Rules, Theorems, and Examples". GeeksforGeeks. 2025-08-06. Retrieved 2025-08-06.
  22. ^ "Boolean Logical Operations" (PDF).
  23. ^ "Boolean Algebra Operations". bob.cs.sonoma.edu. Retrieved 2025-08-06.
  24. ^ "Boolean Algebra" (PDF).
  25. ^ O'Regan, Gerard (2008). A brief history of computing. Springer. p. 33. ISBN 978-1-84800-083-4.
  26. ^ "Elements of Boolean Algebra". www.ee.surrey.ac.uk. Retrieved 2025-08-06.
  27. ^ McGee, Vann, Sentential Calculus Revisited: Boolean Algebra (PDF)
  28. ^ Goodstein, Reuben Louis (2012), "Chapter 4: Sentence Logic", Boolean Algebra, Courier Dover Publications, ISBN 978-0-48615497-8
  29. ^ Venn, John (July 1880). "I. On the Diagrammatic and Mechanical Representation of Propositions and Reasonings" (PDF). The London, Edinburgh, and Dublin Philosophical Magazine and Journal of Science. 5. 10 (59): 1–18. doi:10.1080/14786448008626877. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2025-08-06. [1] [2]
  30. ^ Shannon, Claude (1949). "The Synthesis of Two-Terminal Switching Circuits". Bell System Technical Journal. 28: 59–98. doi:10.1002/j.1538-7305.1949.tb03624.x.
  31. ^ Koppelberg, Sabine (1989). "General Theory of Boolean Algebras". Handbook of Boolean Algebras, Vol. 1 (ed. J. Donald Monk with Robert Bonnet). Amsterdam, Netherlands: North Holland. ISBN 978-0-444-70261-6.
  32. ^ McCune, William; Veroff, Robert; Fitelson, Branden; Harris, Kenneth; Feist, Andrew; Wos, Larry (2002), "Short single axioms for Boolean algebra", Journal of Automated Reasoning, 29 (1): 1–16, doi:10.1023/A:1020542009983, MR 1940227, S2CID 207582048
  33. ^ Allwood, Jens; Andersson, Gunnar-Gunnar; Andersson, Lars-Gunnar; Dahl, Osten (2025-08-06). Logic in Linguistics. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-29174-3.
  34. ^ Hausman, Alan; Kahane, Howard; Tidman, Paul (2010) [2007]. Logic and Philosophy: A Modern Introduction. Wadsworth Cengage Learning. ISBN 978-0-495-60158-6.
  35. ^ Girard, Jean-Yves; Taylor, Paul; Lafont, Yves (1990) [1989]. Proofs and Types. Cambridge University Press (Cambridge Tracts in Theoretical Computer Science, 7). ISBN 978-0-521-37181-0.

Further reading

[edit]

Historical perspective

[edit]
[edit]
带状疱疹是什么 有什么游戏 斑秃吃什么药效果好 开字加一笔是什么字 彷徨是什么意思
六月五号是什么星座 为什么小腿肌肉酸痛 吃什么有助于消化 手指腱鞘炎是什么原因造成的 脚脖子疼是什么原因
俄罗斯信仰什么教 内痔用什么药治最好效果最快 湿气重的人吃什么好 献血前需要注意什么 胆囊炎吃什么药
哦哦是什么意思 邮政编码有什么用 箬叶和粽叶有什么区别 甲状腺球蛋白抗体低说明什么 小孩子头发黄是什么原因
了凡四训讲的是什么qingzhougame.com 刘姥姥和贾府什么关系sscsqa.com 蝴蝶宝贝是什么病hcv7jop5ns1r.cn 什锦是什么意思hcv7jop4ns5r.cn 智齿什么时候长hcv8jop2ns1r.cn
白油是什么油hcv8jop2ns8r.cn 上梁不正下梁歪是什么意思hcv7jop9ns9r.cn 代糖是什么东西hcv8jop1ns0r.cn 反流性食管炎挂什么科hcv8jop5ns7r.cn 虚热是什么意思hcv9jop3ns9r.cn
ppi是什么意思hcv8jop4ns2r.cn 子癫是什么病hcv9jop6ns3r.cn 贵是什么意思hcv7jop5ns2r.cn 泥石流是什么hcv9jop3ns0r.cn 色丁布是什么面料hcv9jop4ns9r.cn
太公是什么意思hcv9jop8ns3r.cn 阿西是什么意思hcv8jop1ns9r.cn 牛肉饺子馅配什么蔬菜hcv9jop4ns9r.cn 吃了避孕药有什么反应hcv8jop4ns0r.cn 吃米饭配什么菜好吃hcv8jop8ns1r.cn
百度